Read More
Date: 25-4-2018
339
Date: 25-4-2018
638
Date: 25-4-2018
395
|
Categories are algebraic structures with many complementary natures, e.g., geometric, logical, computational, combinatorial, just as groups are many-faceted algebraic structures. Eilenberg & Mac Lane (1945) introduced categories in a purely auxiliary fashion, as preparation for what they called functors and natural transformations. The very definition of a category evolved over time, according to the author's chosen goals and metamathematical framework. Eilenberg & Mac Lane at first gave a purely abstract definition of a category, along the lines of the axiomatic definition of a group. Others, starting with Grothendieck (1957) and Freyd (1964), elected for reasons of practicality to define categories in set-theoretic terms.
An alternative approach, that of Lawvere (1963, 1966), begins by characterizing the category of categories, and then stipulates that a category is an object of that universe. This approach, under active development by various mathematicians, logicians and mathematical physicists, lead to what are now called “higher-dimensional categories” (Baez 1997, Baez & Dolan 1998a, Batanin 1998, Leinster 2002, Hermida et al. 2000, 2001, 2002). The very definition of a category is not without philosophical importance, since one of the objections to category theory as a foundational framework is the claim that since categories are defined as sets, category theory cannot provide a philosophically enlightening foundation for mathematics. We will briefly go over some of these definitions, starting with Eilenberg's & Mac Lane's (1945) algebraic definition. However, before going any further, the following definition will be required.
Definition: A mapping e will be called an identity if and only if the existence of any product eα or βe implies that eα = α and βe = β
Definition (Eilenberg & Mac Lane 1945): A category C is an aggregate Ob of abstract elements, called the objects of C, and abstract elements Map, called mappings of the category. The mappings are subject to the following five axioms:
(C1) Given three mappings α1, α2 and α3, the triple product α3(α2α1) is defined if and only if (α3α2)α1 is defined. When either is defined, the associative lawα3(α2α1) = (α3α2)α1holds. This triple product is written α3α2α1.
(C2) The triple product α3α2α1 is defined whenever both products α3α2 and α2α1are defined.
(C3) For each mapping α, there is at least one identity e1 such that αe1 is defined, and at least one identity e2 such that e2α is defined.
(C4) The mapping eX corresponding to each object X is an identity.
(C5) For each identity e there is a unique object X of C such that eX = e.
As Eilenberg & Mac Lane promptly remark, objects play a secondary role and could be entirely omitted from the definition. Doing so, however, would make the manipulation of the applications less convenient. It is practically suitable,and perhaps psychologically more simple to think in terms of mappings and objects. The term “aggregate” is used by Eilenberg & Mac Lane themselves, presumably so as to remain neutral with respect to the background set theory one wants to adopt.
Eilenberg & Mac Lane defined categories in 1945 for reasons of rigor. As they note:
It should be observed first that the whole concept of a category is essentially an auxiliary one; our basic concepts are essentially those of a functor and of natural transformation (…). The idea of a category is required only by the precept that every function should have a definite class as domain and a definite class as range, for the categories are provided as the domains and ranges of functors. Thus one could drop the category concept altogether and adopt an even more intuitive standpoint, in which a functor such as “Hom” is not defined over the category of “all” groups, but for each particular pair of groups which may be given. The standpoint would suffice for applications, inasmuch as none of our developments will involve elaborate constructions on the categories themselves. (1945, chap. 1, par. 6, p. 247)
Things changed in the following ten years, when categories started to be used in homology theory and homological algebra. Mac Lane, Buchsbaum, Grothendieck and Heller were considering categories in which the collections of morphisms between two fixed objects have an additional structure. More specifically, given any two objects X and Y of a category C, the set Hom(X, Y) of morphisms from X to Y form an abelian group. Furthermore, for reasons related to the ways homology and cohomology theories are linked, the definition of a category had to satisfy an additional formal property (which we will leave aside for the moment): it had to be self-dual. These requirements lead to the following definition.
Definition: A category C can be described as a set Ob, whose members are the objects of C, satisfying the following three conditions:
Morphism : For every pair X, Y of objects, there is a set Hom(X, Y), called the morphisms from X to Y in C. If f is a morphism from X to Y, we write f : X → Y.Identity : For every object X, there exists a morphism idX in Hom(X, X), called the identity on X.
Composition : For every triple X, Y and Z of objects, there exists a partial binary operation from Hom(X, Y) × Hom(Y, Z) to Hom(X, Z), called the composition of morphisms in C. If f : X → Y and g : Y → Z, the composition of f and g is notated (g ○ f ) : X → Z.
Identity, morphisms, and composition satisfy two axioms:
Associativity : If f : X → Y, g : Y → Z and h : Z → W, then h ○ (g ○ f) = (h ○ g) ○f.Identity : If f : X → Y, then (idY ○ f) = f and (f ○ idX) = f.
This is the definition one finds in most textbooks of category theory. As such it explicitly relies on a set theoretical background and language. An alternative, suggested by Lawvere in the early sixties, is to develop an adequate language and background framework for a category of categories. We will not present the formal framework here, for it would take us too far from our main concern, but the basic idea is to define what are called weak n-categories (and weak ω-categories), and what had been called categories would then be called weak 1-categories (and sets would be weak 0-categories). (See, for instance, Baez 1997, Makkai 1998, Leinster 2004, Baez & May 2010, Simpson 2011.)
Also in the sixties, Lambek proposed to look at categories as deductive systems. This begins with the notion of a graph, consisting of two classes Arrows and Objects, and two mappings between them, s : Arrows → Objects and t : Arrows → Objects, namely the source and the target mappings. The arrows are usually called the “oriented edges” and the objects “nodes” or “vertices”. Following this, a deductive system is a graph with a specified arrow:
(R1) idX : X → X,
and a binary operation on arrows:
(R2) Given f : X → Y and g : Y → Z, the composition of f and g is (g ○ f) : X → Z.
Of course, the objects of a deductive system are normally thought of as formulas, the arrows are thought of as proofs or deductions, and operations on arrows are thought of asrules of inference. A category is then defined thus:
Definition (Lambek): A category is a deductive system in which the following equations hold between proofs: for all f : X → Y, g : Y → Z and h: Z → W,
(E1) f ○ idX = f, idY ○ f = f, h ○ (g ○ f) = (h ○ g) ○ f.
Thus, by imposing an adequate equivalence relation upon proofs, any deductive system can be turned into a category. It is therefore legitimate to think of a category as an algebraic encoding of a deductive system. This phenomenon is already well-known to logicians, but probably not to its fullest extent. An example of such an algebraic encoding is the Lindenbaum-Tarski algebra, a Boolean algebra corresponding to classical propositional logic. Since a Boolean algebra is a poset, it is also a category. (Notice also that Boolean algebras with appropriate homomorphisms between them form another useful category in logic.) Thus far we have merely a change of vocabulary. Things become more interesting when first-order and higher-order logics are considered. The Lindenbaum-Tarski algebra for these systems, when properly carried out, yields categories, sometimes called “conceptual categories” or “syntactic categories” (Mac Lane & Moerdijk 1992, Makkai & Reyes 1977, Pitts 2000).
|
|
علامات بسيطة في جسدك قد تنذر بمرض "قاتل"
|
|
|
|
|
أول صور ثلاثية الأبعاد للغدة الزعترية البشرية
|
|
|
|
|
مكتبة أمّ البنين النسويّة تصدر العدد 212 من مجلّة رياض الزهراء (عليها السلام)
|
|
|