x
هدف البحث
بحث في العناوين
بحث في اسماء الكتب
بحث في اسماء المؤلفين
اختر القسم
موافق
تاريخ الرياضيات
الاعداد و نظريتها
تاريخ التحليل
تار يخ الجبر
الهندسة و التبلوجي
الرياضيات في الحضارات المختلفة
العربية
اليونانية
البابلية
الصينية
المايا
المصرية
الهندية
الرياضيات المتقطعة
المنطق
اسس الرياضيات
فلسفة الرياضيات
مواضيع عامة في المنطق
الجبر
الجبر الخطي
الجبر المجرد
الجبر البولياني
مواضيع عامة في الجبر
الضبابية
نظرية المجموعات
نظرية الزمر
نظرية الحلقات والحقول
نظرية الاعداد
نظرية الفئات
حساب المتجهات
المتتاليات-المتسلسلات
المصفوفات و نظريتها
المثلثات
الهندسة
الهندسة المستوية
الهندسة غير المستوية
مواضيع عامة في الهندسة
التفاضل و التكامل
المعادلات التفاضلية و التكاملية
معادلات تفاضلية
معادلات تكاملية
مواضيع عامة في المعادلات
التحليل
التحليل العددي
التحليل العقدي
التحليل الدالي
مواضيع عامة في التحليل
التحليل الحقيقي
التبلوجيا
نظرية الالعاب
الاحتمالات و الاحصاء
نظرية التحكم
بحوث العمليات
نظرية الكم
الشفرات
الرياضيات التطبيقية
نظريات ومبرهنات
علماء الرياضيات
500AD
500-1499
1000to1499
1500to1599
1600to1649
1650to1699
1700to1749
1750to1779
1780to1799
1800to1819
1820to1829
1830to1839
1840to1849
1850to1859
1860to1864
1865to1869
1870to1874
1875to1879
1880to1884
1885to1889
1890to1894
1895to1899
1900to1904
1905to1909
1910to1914
1915to1919
1920to1924
1925to1929
1930to1939
1940to the present
علماء الرياضيات
الرياضيات في العلوم الاخرى
بحوث و اطاريح جامعية
هل تعلم
طرائق التدريس
الرياضيات العامة
نظرية البيان
Cantor, G.
المؤلف: Über unendliche, lineare Punktmannigfältigkeiten, Arbeiten zur Mengenlehre aus dem Jahren 1872-1884. Leipzig, Germany: Teubner-Archiv zur Mathematik, 1884.
المصدر: المرجع الالكتروني للمعلوماتيه
الجزء والصفحة: ...
5-1-2022
1443
In common usage, an ordinal number is an adjective which describes the numerical position of an object, e.g., first, second, third, etc.
In formal set theory, an ordinal number (sometimes simply called an "ordinal" for short) is one of the numbers in Georg Cantor's extension of the whole numbers. An ordinal number is defined as the order type of a well ordered set (Dauben 1990, p. 199; Moore 1982, p. 52; Suppes 1972, p. 129). Finite ordinal numbers are commonly denoted using arabic numerals, while transfinite ordinals are denoted using lower case Greek letters.
It is easy to see that every finite totally ordered set is well ordered. Any two totally ordered sets with elements (for a nonnegative integer) are order isomorphic, and therefore have the same order type (which is also an ordinal number). The ordinals for finite sets are denoted 0, 1, 2, 3, ..., i.e., the integers one less than the corresponding nonnegative integers.
The first transfinite ordinal, denoted , is the order type of the set of nonnegative integers (Dauben 1990, p. 152; Moore 1982, p. viii; Rubin 1967, pp. 86 and 177; Suppes 1972, p. 128). This is the "smallest" of Cantor's transfinite numbers, defined to be the smallest ordinal number greater than the ordinal number of the whole numbers. Conway and Guy (1996) denote it with the notation .
From the definition of ordinal comparison, it follows that the ordinal numbers are a well ordered set. In order of increasing size, the ordinal numbers are 0, 1, 2, ..., , , , ..., , , .... The notation of ordinal numbers can be a bit counterintuitive, e.g., even though , . The cardinal number of the set of countable ordinal numbers is denoted (aleph-1).
If is a well ordered set with ordinal number , then the set of all ordinals is order isomorphic to . This provides the motivation to define an ordinal as the set of all ordinals less than itself. John von Neumann defined a set to be an ordinal number iff
1. If is a member of , then is a proper subset of
2. If and are members of then one of the following is true: , is a member of , or is a member of .
3. If is a nonempty proper subset of , then there exists a member of such that the intersection is empty.
(Rubin 1967, p. 176; Ciesielski 1997, p. 44). This is the standard representation of ordinals. In this representation,
symbol | elements | description |
0 | empty set | |
1 | set of one element | |
2 | set of two elements | |
3 | set of three elements | |
set of all finite ordinals | ||
set of all countable ordinals | ||
set of all countable and ordinals | ||
set all finite ordinals and ordinals for all nonnegative integers | ||
Rubin (1967, p. 272) provides a nice definition of the ordinals.
Since for any ordinal , the union is a bigger ordinal , there is no largest ordinal, and the class of all ordinals is therefore a proper class (as shown by the Burali-Forti paradox).
Ordinal numbers have some other rather peculiar properties. The sum of two ordinal numbers can take on two different values, the sum of three can take on five values. The first few terms of this sequence are 2, 5, 13, 33, 81, 193, 449, , , , , , ..., namely 2, 5, 13, 33, 81, 193, 449, 1089, 2673, 6561, 15633, 37249, ... (Conway and Guy 1996, OEIS A005348). The sum of ordinals has either or possible answers for (Conway and Guy 1996).
is the same as , but is equal to . is larger than any number of the form , is larger than , and so on.
There exist ordinal numbers which cannot be constructed from smaller ones by finite additions, multiplications, and exponentiations. These ordinals obey Cantor's equation. The first such ordinal is
The next is
then follow , , ..., , , ..., , ..., , , ..., , , ..., , ..., , ..., , ..., , ..., , ..., , ..., , ..., , ..., , ..., , ... (Conway and Guy 1996).
Ordinal addition, ordinal multiplication, and ordinal exponentiation can all be defined. Although these definitions also work perfectly well for order types, this does not seem to be commonly done. There are two methods commonly used to define operations on the ordinals: one is using sets, and the other is inductively.
REFERENCES:
Cantor, G. Über unendliche, lineare Punktmannigfältigkeiten, Arbeiten zur Mengenlehre aus dem Jahren 1872-1884. Leipzig, Germany: Teubner-Archiv zur Mathematik, 1884.
Ciesielski, K. Set Theory for the Working Mathematician. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
Conway, J. H. and Guy, R. K. "Cantor's Ordinal Numbers." In The Book of Numbers. New York: Springer-Verlag, pp. 266-267 and 274, 1996.
Dauben, J. W. Georg Cantor: His Mathematics and Philosophy of the Infinite. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1990.
Moore, G. H. Zermelo's Axiom of Choice: Its Origin, Development, and Influence. New York: Springer-Verlag, 1982.
Rubin, J. E. Set Theory for the Mathematician. New York: Holden-Day, 1967.
Suppes, P. Axiomatic Set Theory. New York: Dover, 1972.
Sloane, N. J. A. Sequence A005348/M1435 in "The On-Line Encyclopedia of Integer Sequences."