Read More
Date: 13-2-2022
![]()
Date: 12-2-2022
![]()
Date: 13-2-2022
![]() |
The set of terms of first-order logic (also known as first-order predicate calculus) is defined by the following rules:
1. A variable is a term.
2. If is an
-place function symbol (with
) and
, ...,
are terms, then
is a term.
If is an
-place predicate symbol (again with
) and
, ...,
are terms, then
is an atomic statement.
Consider the sentential formulas and
, where
is a sentential formula,
is the universal quantifier ("for all"), and
is the existential quantifier ("there exists").
is called the scope of the respective quantifier, and any occurrence of variable
in the scope of a quantifier is bound by the closest
or
. The variable
is free in the formula
if at least one of its occurrences in
is not bound by any quantifier within
.
The set of sentential formulas of first-order predicate calculus is defined by the following rules:
1. Any atomic statement is a sentential formula.
2. If and
are sentential formulas, then
(NOT
),
(
AND
),
(
OR
), and
(
implies
) are sentential formulas (cf. propositional calculus).
3. If is a sentential formula in which
is a free variable, then
and
are sentential formulas.
In formulas of first-order predicate calculus, all variables are object variables serving as arguments of functions and predicates. (In second-order predicate calculus, variables may denote predicates, and quantifiers may apply to variables standing for predicates.) The set of axiom schemata of first-order predicate calculus is comprised of the axiom schemata of propositional calculus together with the two following axiom schemata:
(1) |
|
(2) |
where is any sentential formula in which
occurs free,
is a term,
is the result of substituting
for the free occurrences of
in sentential formula
, and all occurrences of all variables in
are free in
.
Rules of inference in first-order predicate calculus are the Modus Ponens and the two following rules:
(3) |
|
(4) |
where is any sentential formula in which
occurs as a free variable,
does not occur as a free variable in formula
, and the notation means that if the formula above the line is a theorem formally deducted from axioms by application of inference rules, then the sentential formula below the line is also a formal theorem.
Similarly to propositional calculus, rules for introduction and elimination of and
can be derived in first-order predicate calculus. For example, the following rule holds provided that
is the result of substituting variable
for the free occurrences of
in sentential formula
and all occurrences of
resulting from this substitution are free in
,
(5) |
Gödel's completeness theorem established equivalence between valid formulas of first-order predicate calculus and formal theorems of first-order predicate calculus. In contrast to propositional calculus, use of truth tables does not work for finding valid sentential formulas in first-order predicate calculus because its truth tables are infinite. However, Gödel's completeness theorem opens a way to determine validity, namely by proof.
Chang, C.-L. and Lee, R. C.-T. Symbolic Logic and Mechanical Theorem Proving. New York: Academic Press, 1997.
Kleene, S. C. Mathematical Logic. New York: Dover, 2002.Mendelson, E. Introduction to Mathematical Logic, 4th ed. London: Chapman & Hall, p. 12, 1997.
|
|
منها نحت القوام.. ازدياد إقبال الرجال على عمليات التجميل
|
|
|
|
|
دراسة: الذكاء الاصطناعي يتفوق على البشر في مراقبة القلب
|
|
|
|
|
هيئة الصحة والتعليم الطبي في العتبة الحسينية تحقق تقدما بارزا في تدريب الكوادر الطبية في العراق
|
|
|